Læknablaðið

Árgangur

Læknablaðið - 15.10.1989, Blaðsíða 48

Læknablaðið - 15.10.1989, Blaðsíða 48
310 LÆKNABLAÐIÐ Thomas Beauchamp and theologian James Childress, Principles of Biomedical Ethics, Oxford University Press, 1978 (second edition, 1983), and are discussed by Raanan Gillon, Philosophical Medical Ethics, John Wylie and Sons, 1986. See also The Belmont Report: Ethical Principles and Guidelines for the Protection of Human Subjects. DHEW pub. no. (os) 78-0012, Washington, D.C., 1978. 5. Several delegates felt that »respect for life« should be added as a fifth principle coequal with the other four. 6. The term competent (and all variations such as incompetent, competence, etc.) is used throughout this statement in its general ethical sense indicating adequate decision-making capacity for the specific decision or class of decisions under discussion and not in its narrower legal sense. 7. It should be remembered that in some religious traditions (e.g. Orthodox Judaism) the right to refuse lifesaving treatment is not recognized as morally valid. 8. Some delegates felt that it was not at all clear that legalizing such intervention was against the public interest, especially in light of confirmation in repeated polls (most recently Roper, 1988; Harris 1987; and »A Survey of Opinions and Experiences of Colorado Physicians,» 1988) that a majority of the U.S. public and a substantial minority of physicians state that there are circumstances under which a physician should accede (or be legally permitted to accede) to a patient’s request for a lethal dose of medication. Others felt that legalizing such intervention was not only contrary to public interest but a violation of »basic morality«. See dissents. 9. Some of the delegates argued that in situations of real doubt as to whether a proposed treatment is in the patient’s interest, the choice should be to withhold that treatment (the common bias toward treatment - whether resting on a technological imperative or a vitalist assumption - being unjustified). Others felt that although physicians should never treat merely because a treatment is available, in some cases where it was not clear what the interests of the patient were, prolonging life of a quality that most patients would accept would be justified. All delegates rejected the simple vitalist assumption that prolonging life is always in a patient’s interest. 10. Examining the rationale for the statements of family, friends, and caregivers is an important part of this process, including consideration of the possibility of conflicts of interest with the patient. Care should be taken, however, to guard against discounting the views of disagreeing parties merely because they are disagreeable or inarticulate. 11. For cases where treatment would not be physiologically futile, but nonetheless futile in the context of the whole condition, the same advice should apply as in Part I: Requests for Treatment. 12. Some delegates argued that continued treatment of PVS patients can be justified by the benefit such treatment would offer to others (e.g., to parents or close relatives). Others argued that a PVS patient should never be treated solely for the benefit of others. Both deontological and utilitarian arguments were adduced to support this contention. Still other delegates argued that the continued treatment of a PVS patient for the benefit of others may be justifiable if such treatment were continued only for a short time; for example, until the diagnosis can be established with a high degree of certainty or until tha family has had a reasonable amount of time to recognize the hopelessness of the situation. See dissents. 13. Third person quality of life judgments are judgments made grammatically and logically in the third person - i.e., judgments about the quality of »his« or »her« life vis-a-vis first person judgments about the quality of »my« life. 14. This form of third person quality of life judgment must be carefully distinguished from third person quality of life judgments based on concepts of minimal social worth, which all delegates felt are seldom or never morally justifiable as a basis for medical decision making in individual cases. 15. It is recognized, however, that the language of benefits and burdens will not by itself resolve the most difficult dilemmas, since irreconcilable differences can always be reexpressed in terms of a claim that their opponents have overestimated burdens and have underestimated benefits, or vice versa. These terms are nonetheless useful in helping to focus on clinically significant variables and to avoid employing judgments of social worth. 16. A useful summary and discussion of these mechanisms appears in Guidelines on the
Blaðsíða 1
Blaðsíða 2
Blaðsíða 3
Blaðsíða 4
Blaðsíða 5
Blaðsíða 6
Blaðsíða 7
Blaðsíða 8
Blaðsíða 9
Blaðsíða 10
Blaðsíða 11
Blaðsíða 12
Blaðsíða 13
Blaðsíða 14
Blaðsíða 15
Blaðsíða 16
Blaðsíða 17
Blaðsíða 18
Blaðsíða 19
Blaðsíða 20
Blaðsíða 21
Blaðsíða 22
Blaðsíða 23
Blaðsíða 24
Blaðsíða 25
Blaðsíða 26
Blaðsíða 27
Blaðsíða 28
Blaðsíða 29
Blaðsíða 30
Blaðsíða 31
Blaðsíða 32
Blaðsíða 33
Blaðsíða 34
Blaðsíða 35
Blaðsíða 36
Blaðsíða 37
Blaðsíða 38
Blaðsíða 39
Blaðsíða 40
Blaðsíða 41
Blaðsíða 42
Blaðsíða 43
Blaðsíða 44
Blaðsíða 45
Blaðsíða 46
Blaðsíða 47
Blaðsíða 48
Blaðsíða 49
Blaðsíða 50
Blaðsíða 51
Blaðsíða 52
Blaðsíða 53
Blaðsíða 54
Blaðsíða 55
Blaðsíða 56
Blaðsíða 57
Blaðsíða 58
Blaðsíða 59
Blaðsíða 60
Blaðsíða 61
Blaðsíða 62
Blaðsíða 63
Blaðsíða 64
Blaðsíða 65
Blaðsíða 66
Blaðsíða 67
Blaðsíða 68

x

Læknablaðið

Beinir tenglar

Ef þú vilt tengja á þennan titil, vinsamlegast notaðu þessa tengla:

Tengja á þennan titil: Læknablaðið
https://timarit.is/publication/986

Tengja á þetta tölublað:

Tengja á þessa síðu:

Tengja á þessa grein:

Vinsamlegast ekki tengja beint á myndir eða PDF skjöl á Tímarit.is þar sem slíkar slóðir geta breyst án fyrirvara. Notið slóðirnar hér fyrir ofan til að tengja á vefinn.